What Does the Reason Say? : Ibn al-Nafīs’ Problematization of Natural Reason
What Does the Reason Say? : Ibn al-Nafīs’ Problematization of Natural Reason
What Does the Reason Say? : Ibn al-Nafīs’ Problematization of Natural Reason

Introduction
The thirteenth
century polymath Ibn al-Nafīs (d. 1288) found himself in an environment where
the falasifa privileged themselves through relegating “theological
sources” as secondary and, even, somewhat depraved. The basic argument of the falasifa
perhaps could be summarized this way: reason itself is enough in unearthing the
truth, and religion is for simpletons, if not entirely superfluous. Ibn
al-Nafīs issues a rejoinder to this narrative in his Risālat Fādil ibn Nātiq
(The book of Fadil ibn Natiq), hereafter Risālat, also known as al-Risālat
al-Kāmiliyya fī al-Sīrat al-Nabawiyya (The Treatise Relating to Kāmil on
the Life-History of the Prophet).
In this essay,
I propose a novel reading of Ibn al-Nafīs’ work and argue that his work
has problematized the category of reason itself by denying it an independent,
extra-contextual existence. In other words, it is my claim that the Risālat demonstrates
that reason itself is subject to the social environment in which it is thought
about, communicated to one another, and its boundaries are (re-)negotiated. One
important caveat is that I am not setting out to discover Ibn al-Nafīs’ intent,
that is to say whether he indeed did intend to offer this particular reading
that I am proposing.
The radical
potential of such a reading of Ibn al-Nafis’ Risālat lies in denying any
race, epistemology, socioeconomic class, normative orientation, or scholarly
class, to name only a few groups, any (false) sense of superiority through an
exclusive claim to objective, pre-political, natural facts. This
anti-foundationalist reading of the Risālat forces grand claims to
natural truth to, firstly, provincialize themselves, and, secondly, enter a
more honest conversation with competing epistemologies. In the contemporary world,
this reading of Ibn al-Nafis disrupts the dominant trend of marshalling the logic
of natural reason to marginalize other epistemologies.
The first
section of the essay sets the stage; it outlines the background against which
Ibn al-Nafis produced the Risālat, as well as a synopsis of the text. The
second section deals with Ibn al-Nafis’ unmasking reason’s social groundedness
– to the point that the reason versus revelation dichotomy collapses. In the
final section, I underscore the importance of such a reading of Ibn al-Nafis’
work in guiding our approach to truth and ways of knowing it, especially vis-à-vis
the question of power.
Setting the
Stage
Ibn al-Nafis
found himself in an environment wherein the falasifa, beginning with Ibn
Sina and drawing upon the Greek philosophical tradition, privileged human
reason over revelation. They insisted that truth is knowable through reason
alone and revelation is at best a crude attempt at transmitting it to the
uninitiated masses. They denied that revelation is a valid source of knowledge
(Marmura 1983: 87-102, Rahman 1958: 42-45, Abrahamov 1998). The Andalusian scholar
Ibn Ṭufayl (d. 1186), working within this tradition, advanced a theory of
rational mysticism in which religious truths, including “a mystical vision of
God,” are harmonized with the discoveries made by falsafa, but
revelation ultimatelt remained redundant (Fancy 2009: 220).
Ibn Ṭufayl’s Ḥayy
ibn Yaqzan is the text against which Ibn al-Nafis’s Risālat set
itself up. As such, an account of the Risālat must begin with an
appreciation of Ibn Ṭufayl’s work. Ibn Ṭufayl’s Ḥayy ibn Yaqẓān is a story
of Ḥayy, a human who naturally comes into being – i.e., without being
born to human parents – in an isolated island, although an alternative version
of Ḥayy’s birth contained in the story says that he is abandoned by his parents.
In the island, a gazelle took care of Ḥayy until the former dies. Ḥayy, without
the knowledge of human language, embarks on a journey of rational inquiry,
leading him to a range of discoveries, including the knowledge of the existence
the Creator. Through reason alone, he also deduces the necessity of worshiping
the Creator. Suddenly, Ḥayy comes into contact with the human society as a ship
reached the shore of the hitherto solitary island. His interaction with human teaches
him the human language and religion. He concludes that the truth he discovered
through his independent rational inquiry is in agreement with the essential
truth encapsulated in the religion, although the former is a higher and purer
kind of truth. Travelling to the human society, Ḥayy hopes to enlighten his
fellow humans but is frustrated by the latter’s inability to outgrow the
so-called literalism of the revealed religion. He then self-exiles himself to
his island (Ibn Tufayl 2009).
Kāmil, the
protagonist of Ibn al-Nafis’ Risālat, shares a number of similarities
with Ḥayy. Like Ḥayy, Kāmil also naturally comes into existence in an
isolated island and without any human parents. The text does not provide any
alternative version of his birth. Kāmil then observes his surroundings and makes
a series of discoveries, including of the existence of the God. Like Ḥayy, Kāmil
also encounters a group of humans with whom he travels to the human society. This
is the point where Kāmil’s path diverges from that of Ḥayy. Although Kāmil’s
self-made discoveries perfectly align with what he comes to know about the
revealed religion of the human society, he learns a lot more from that
society about the specificities of that religion, with which he rationally agrees
after reflecting upon them. The text does not mention anything about Kāmil’s
return to a solitary life. It does not elicit the idea that Kāmil thinks ill of
the knowledge gleaned from his interaction with humans, who had access to that
knowledge through the revealed religion. In other words, the superiority of Ḥayy
and his access to purer knowledge through pure reason vis-à-vis commoners and
their access to dumbed down knowledge through revelation is absent in Ibn
al-Nafis’ Risālat (al-Nafis 1968; see also Fancy 2009, Lauri 2017).
With this concise
background in mind, I turn to the issue of problematization of the
reason-revelation binary in Ibn al-Nafis’ text.
Problematizing
the Reason-Revelation Binary
The striking
similarity, as well as the differences, between Ibn al-Nafis’ Kāmil and Ibn Ṭufayl’s
Ḥayy is not lost on scholars. While Ḥayy is often described as a self-taught
philosopher, Kāmil is termed as a self-taught theologian (Fancy 2009: 220-21).
Ibn Ṭufayl’s Ḥayy
exemplifies the limits of the revealed, organized religion and scholarly class
that the religion gives birth to and, in turn, is guarded by. Ḥayy promotes a
mode knowing, which, notwithstanding its much-stressed conformity with the
essence of the revealed religion, is independent of any prophetic revelation.
Not only is the truth made knowable through pure reason, it also is posited as
a superior form of truth – truth in its purest form – in contrast with the
dumbed down truth of the revealed religion, which is for the laymen (Germann
2016, Fancy 2009).
Kāmil, on the
other hand, inverses the equation. Although Kāmil, like Ḥayy, makes rational
enquiries, his discoveries can go, within the metaphysical realm, only as far
as rationalizing the existence of the Creator. The intricate details of the
religion reveal themselves to Kāmil only through the humans with whom he comes
into contact. This limits his pure reason, which is then juxtaposed with the vast
and possibly all-encompassing knowledge of the revealed religion that his
encountered humans possessed. Thus, Kāmil’s rationality is indebted, rather
than superior, to the revealed religion of the human society. In this sense,
Fancy (2009) argues that Ibn al-Nafis does not merely marshal rationalist
arguments in defense of theology but he also highlights limits of reason to make
theology indispensable to knowledge in its totality. Fancy, therefore, denies
that Kāmil’s journey could be reduced to a rationalist defense for theology
(2009: 221).
I, however,
argue that a more important contribution of the text is how it problematizes
the concept of an extra-contextual reason. The description of Kāmil as a
self-taught theologian who discovers the orthodox Islamic tenets by using pure
reason, a portrait that Nancy is opposed to, should not be dismissed a priori. Kāmil
certainly deploys reason to reach the conclusions deemed traditional religious
beliefs, prompting the translators Schacht and Meyerhof to declare Kāmil a
self-taught theologian (al-Nafis 1968). Even when Kāmil harmonizes his rational
thoughts with what he came to know through his contact with the human society,
he does so by putting reason to use. If it is pure reason that drives Kāmil to
(organized and revealed) religion and Ḥayy away from it, the question that
arises is this: what does the reason say? Asked differently, does reason have
an existence outside the context in which it appears?
If both Ḥayy
and Kāmil are using pure reason but ending up in different shores, it may mean one
of the two things. Either the concept of an extra-contextual reason with a
defined linear feature is wrong or one of the two protagonists made at least
one mistake at some point in their journey that led them to different
conclusions. If we entertain the second possibility, we are confronted by yet
another dilemma: how do we mediate between two claims on reason? If either Ḥayy
or Kāmil is being irrational, we can only know it through a recourse to a third,
neutral rational approach. But doing so is an impossibility because the
existence of a yet another rationality would render both Ḥayy and Kāmil’s
respective rationalities inferior and incomplete. And if we are to judge both
of them against one of their experiences, the result will always favor the individual
whose experience we are using as the yardstick. In short, the dilemma here is
no less complicated than mediating between competing theologies, or telling a
soothsayer from a prophet.
In other words,
the categories of reason and religion, as well as the rivalries between
different sets of actors based on the distinction between the two, fall apart
insofar as both reason and religion become amorphous. If reason is as arbitrary
and subjective as religion, we might even ask what useful function the
distinction between the two plays.
Fancy’s
objection to viewing Kāmil as marshalling reason in defense of revelation also
contains an outstanding issue. Fancy admits that Kāmil “becomes aware of the
existence of God” through pure reason (2009: 230), although he learns about the
specifics of this God after his encounter with the human society. The latter
part takes a privileged position in Fancy’s investigation into Kāmil’s
epistemology. However, I propose that the question we should be asking instead
is the following. What guarantee do we have that pure reason would lead us to conclude
that a God exists, let alone the Muslim God that both Ḥayy and Kāmil
discover? Before I return to this point in the succeeding section, it is
worthwhile to appreciate Fancy’s treatment of the Risālat, building upon
which Lauri concludes that “Ibn al-Nafis would have probably shared our
conviction of the inherently collaborative nature of scholarly activity.” What
he means by that is Ibn al-Nafis “shows purely self-relying reason to be
insufficient, bringing it again to its societal and testimonial dimensions” (2017:
297). The following section fleshes out this concept and places it in the
context of debates over the legitimacy of experiences of marginalized groups as
legitimate knowledge.
Social
Groundedness of Reason
Social
scientists often debate the human condition sans the corrupting influence of
the society. In order to isolate societal influences from the inbuilt
personality of a character, they have initiated a debate on nature versus
nurture. Like Ibn Ṭufayl and Ibn al-Nafis have allowed Ḥayy and Kāmil
respectively to be found and grown up in a solitary state, social scientists
have also studied cases as closely resembling Ḥayy and Kāmil as possible. The
results of those studies show that blank slates like Ḥayy and Kāmil remain
blank slates if not otherwise tempered with. Put differently, without
socialization, individuals come to know next to nothing simply by observing
their surroundings (Davis 1940, 1947). Studies on even identical twins
demonstrate that their personalities depend in large parts on the environment
in which they grew up (Holden 1980, 1987).
Nevertheless,
actors with different persuasions often cash in on the charm of positing
something as natural. For instance, Christian philosopher/theologian Abū Qurrah
(d. 825) offers the story of the hidden king, which belongs to the same genre
as Ḥayy and Kāmil’s. The story follows a similar type of rational enquiry from
the scratch that confirms the Christian faith tradition (Griffith 1994). It is
not only the religiously oriented who want to impose their will on the blank
slate and call it the natural disposition. John Rawls (1971), widely regarded
as the father of modern liberalism, also speaks in similar terms when he
formulates his theory. The whole philosophical terrain of natural law is
inundated with thinkers trying to advance a certain agenda by tying that to
nature (McIlroy 2019).
Calling
a truth-claim natural gives that claim an edge over its competitor(s). But the
hollowness of such a lazy attempt at avoiding scrutiny by simply invoking terms
like nature and reason is laid bare when it faces similar counter-claims. Intellectual
gymnastics practiced by thinkers with different persuasions lead us to conclude
what I have already stated before: there is no extra-contextual meaning, shape,
or form of reason, or of nature for that matter.
A suspicion
towards truth-claims masquerading themselves as natural underlies contemporary
Western critical scholarship that exposes multifaceted ways partisan objectives
hide within the so-called natural (Bock 1994; 2019; Weiss 2016). They demonstrate,
for example, that Lockean notion of natural law functions as a justification
for colonial land-grabbing in the Americas (Arneil 1992). Interestingly, scholarly
inquiry into Ibn Ṭufayl and Ibn al-Nafis’ impact on the formation of Lockean
natural law, as well as its associate classical liberalism (Russell 1993), is
often uncritical of this instrumentalization of the naturals. That said, feminist
scholars have highlighted the androcentrism embedded in the Rawlsian blank
slate (Okin 2005). Black scholarship carefully highlights the White accent with
which Rawlsian natural reason speaks (Mills 2009). And there have been
accusations that Rawlsian liberalism facilitates Islamophobia (Khan 2017).
What
appears to be natural in a narrative is a consequence of the construction of
that narrative. Put differently, one man’s natural is another man’s artificial,
arbitrary, or contingent.
The
appeal to nature is an attempt to solve the problem of infinite regress the
same way God can be and is invoked to solve the same. In both cases, the task
of covering up the lack of a foundation is relegated to entities like nature
and God, which have no foundations themselves. The falasifa, through
their advocacy of the natural religion and natural reason, engage in a power
play with the ecclesiastical class. But what the natural religion is and
natural reason says remains, as I have tried to demonstrate, as
contested a terrain as that of religion. It is perhaps not a coincident that in
the absence of a secular age, both Ḥayy and Kāmil reasonably believe in God.
That reason, however, is perhaps conditioned by the historical and cultural milieu
that forecloses atheism to be reasonable, or even an option for that matter
(see Taylor 2007). In contrast, A modern author, using a similar writing style,
would probably endorse the opposite, i.e., the non-existence of God, as the natural/reasonable
conclusion.
Ibn
al-Nafis’ foremost contribution, in this sense, is that he forces the modern
reader to humble himself/herself by acknowledging that his/her reason is
identical to a believer’s beliefs. There is nothing separating reason from
belief except how they are named, grouped, and approached (or not) in
particular historical and cultural milieus. In many (but not all) ways, Ibn
al-Nafis faced the same conundrum as many moderns face. Ibn al-Nafis’
adversaries sought to supress a body of knowledge, mode of reasoning, and
peoples associated with them by terming them inferior, if not outright
illegitimate (Fancy 2009). In modernity, women and people of color, among
others, are struggling with this gate-keeping attitudes suppressing so-called
unreasonable experiences and beliefs from the socially legitimate body of
knowledge (see Fricker 2007). Ibn al-Nafis’ Kāmil in this regard stands as a
solemn reminder that at the core of the tension is not any pre-political,
natural truth but an intense political competition over marking, mapping, and
shaping what is presented as natural or reasonable.
This
anti-foundationalist reading of Ibn al-Nafis’ Risālat confirms Fish’s
assertation that “questions of fact, truth, correctness, validity, and clarity
can neither be posed nor answered in reference to some extracontextual,
ahistorical, nonsituational reality (1989: 345). This reading of Ibn al-Nafis
forces us to be more self-aware about our truth-claims and engage with rival
truth-claims more honestly instead of simply dismissing them by categorizing
them as unnatural. What passes as natural at any particular point in time and
space curvature is therefore a matter of discursive construction. And the
discursive construction becomes dominant in a society is reflective of the
power relations in that society (see Srinivasan 2019). This is the lesson we
can draw from Kāmil’s socially grounded reason.
Conclusion
Ibn al-Nafis’
intervention in the debate with the falasifa through his Risālat has
the liberating potential for the marginalized groups and their respective
epistemologies. His text problematizes the idea of a natural reason and
demonstrates that reason gains its meaning, shape, and form within a certain
milieu, beyond which it has no validity. It lays bare the impasse the politics
of attributing to something the adjective natural or rational as a way of shutting
down debates. The critique of natural reason as a depoliticizing tool allows
for alternative imaginations and facilitates bracketed knowledge-systems
to be taken seriously. It highlights the contingencies and power relations responsible
for the rise and fall of an idea or epistemology, thus enabling critique of the
dominant narrative(s), as well as eliciting hope for change.
You May Add Comment Now.

